Theftz22
Smash Lord
It is a classic Kantian moral principle that if it is the case that x ought to be done, then it is the case that x can be done.
Intuitively, it seems odd to say that we could have a moral obligation to do something that that cannot be done. But on second look, you might think that moral principles are things that ought to be followed regardless of whether or not you actually can. A principle doesn't cease to be true because it cannot be fulfilled. I don't have any strong inclination either way in terms of the intuitiveness of the Kantian claim.
Can the Kantian claim be grounded in various ethical systems? Ironically, utilitarianism is perhaps the easiest ethical system on which to ground the Kantian claim. Consider the following argument:
1. If utilitarianism is true, x ought to be done if and only if x maximizes utility.
2. If x cannot be done, x does not maximize utility.
Given these two premises, it is derivable that if utilitarianism is true, then if x ought to be done, then x can be done. Here's the logic:
1. If p, then q iff r
2. If ~s, then ~r
3. If p, then (if ~r, then ~q) (from 1 by the def of biconditionals)
4. If p, then (if ~s, then ~q) (2+3 by transitivity)
5. If p, then (if q, then s) (contrapositive of 4)
Thus the final conclusion is, if utilitarianism is truen, then if x ought to be done, x can be done.
Looking at the 2 premises, each is obviously true. Premise 1 is just the definition of utilitarianism. And 2 is obvious because in order for x to maximize utility, x must be actualized, otherwise no maximization is actualized. But if x can't be done, then x can't be actualized. To put the argument more colloquially, an action won't make the world a better place unless it's performed. So if it can't be performed, it can't make the world a better place. But on utilitarianism, an action ought to be done if and only if it makes the world a better place. So on utilitarianism, if an action ought to be done, it must be the place that it can be done, or else it couldn't make the world a better place.
It is ironic that it is easiest to ground the kantian principle on a consequentialism that is radically opposed to the deontology of kant. Another ethical system on which the kantian claim is easily grounded is divine command theory. Here's the argument:
1. If divine command theory is true, x ought to be done if and only if x is commanded by god.
2. If x cannot be done, god would not command x.
The logical form of the derivation is then identical to the previous one, so I will omit it. Again, premise 1 is just the definition of divine command theory. Premise 2 is need of further argument however. One such argument that might be given in favor of premise 2 is that god holds us accountable for not obeying his commands. But it would be evil for god to hold us accountable for not obeying commands that couldn't be obeyed. Thus, given that god is omnibenevolent, it follows that god wouldn't make commands that couldn't be obeyed. Another argument that could be given is that god would have no reason to issue a command that could not be obeyed. God, being omniscient, foreknows for any given command whether it can be obeyed. But then what would be the purpose of issuing such a command, knowing it cannot be obeyed? Thus, given that god acts only with sufficient reason to act, god would not issue commands that could not be obeyed.
I cannot see any other systems on which the kantian claim is easily grounded. But, can we ground the claim appealing to more general moral principles that are accepted on every ethical system? I think we can, and here's the proof:
1. If x ought to be done, agents are morally accountable for failing to do x.
2. If x can't be done, agents are not morally accountable for failing to do x.
These propositions entail that ought entails can:
1. If p, then q
2. If r, then ~q
3. If q, then ~r (contrapositive of 2)
4. If p, then ~r (1+3 by transitivity)
The conclusion is that if x ought to be done, then x can be done. Both premises are eminently plausible. As for 1, I can't make sense of the notion of "ought", if not in the sense that you would be morally accountable for not doing it. That is just what one means by "moral duty". As for 2, if x can't be done, then one is not accountable in any sense for failing to do x, because it is not in your causal capacity to do x, and therefore you are not responsible or accountable for failing to do x. And therefore one is certainly not morally accountable for failing to do x.
I think then that there are good general moral considerations for believing that ought entails can. But, when examining specific ethical systems, it is hard to ground that claim except on utilitarianism or divine command theory. This may be thought of as constituting evidence against ethical systems other than those two. Further, the claim could be furnished in an interesting kantian moral argument for the existence of god. For it could be argued that we ought to bring about the greatest good. But, if god does not exist, then we cannot bring about the greatest good. Conjoined with the claim that ought entails can, this would imply the existence of god.
All food for thought.
Intuitively, it seems odd to say that we could have a moral obligation to do something that that cannot be done. But on second look, you might think that moral principles are things that ought to be followed regardless of whether or not you actually can. A principle doesn't cease to be true because it cannot be fulfilled. I don't have any strong inclination either way in terms of the intuitiveness of the Kantian claim.
Can the Kantian claim be grounded in various ethical systems? Ironically, utilitarianism is perhaps the easiest ethical system on which to ground the Kantian claim. Consider the following argument:
1. If utilitarianism is true, x ought to be done if and only if x maximizes utility.
2. If x cannot be done, x does not maximize utility.
Given these two premises, it is derivable that if utilitarianism is true, then if x ought to be done, then x can be done. Here's the logic:
1. If p, then q iff r
2. If ~s, then ~r
3. If p, then (if ~r, then ~q) (from 1 by the def of biconditionals)
4. If p, then (if ~s, then ~q) (2+3 by transitivity)
5. If p, then (if q, then s) (contrapositive of 4)
Thus the final conclusion is, if utilitarianism is truen, then if x ought to be done, x can be done.
Looking at the 2 premises, each is obviously true. Premise 1 is just the definition of utilitarianism. And 2 is obvious because in order for x to maximize utility, x must be actualized, otherwise no maximization is actualized. But if x can't be done, then x can't be actualized. To put the argument more colloquially, an action won't make the world a better place unless it's performed. So if it can't be performed, it can't make the world a better place. But on utilitarianism, an action ought to be done if and only if it makes the world a better place. So on utilitarianism, if an action ought to be done, it must be the place that it can be done, or else it couldn't make the world a better place.
It is ironic that it is easiest to ground the kantian principle on a consequentialism that is radically opposed to the deontology of kant. Another ethical system on which the kantian claim is easily grounded is divine command theory. Here's the argument:
1. If divine command theory is true, x ought to be done if and only if x is commanded by god.
2. If x cannot be done, god would not command x.
The logical form of the derivation is then identical to the previous one, so I will omit it. Again, premise 1 is just the definition of divine command theory. Premise 2 is need of further argument however. One such argument that might be given in favor of premise 2 is that god holds us accountable for not obeying his commands. But it would be evil for god to hold us accountable for not obeying commands that couldn't be obeyed. Thus, given that god is omnibenevolent, it follows that god wouldn't make commands that couldn't be obeyed. Another argument that could be given is that god would have no reason to issue a command that could not be obeyed. God, being omniscient, foreknows for any given command whether it can be obeyed. But then what would be the purpose of issuing such a command, knowing it cannot be obeyed? Thus, given that god acts only with sufficient reason to act, god would not issue commands that could not be obeyed.
I cannot see any other systems on which the kantian claim is easily grounded. But, can we ground the claim appealing to more general moral principles that are accepted on every ethical system? I think we can, and here's the proof:
1. If x ought to be done, agents are morally accountable for failing to do x.
2. If x can't be done, agents are not morally accountable for failing to do x.
These propositions entail that ought entails can:
1. If p, then q
2. If r, then ~q
3. If q, then ~r (contrapositive of 2)
4. If p, then ~r (1+3 by transitivity)
The conclusion is that if x ought to be done, then x can be done. Both premises are eminently plausible. As for 1, I can't make sense of the notion of "ought", if not in the sense that you would be morally accountable for not doing it. That is just what one means by "moral duty". As for 2, if x can't be done, then one is not accountable in any sense for failing to do x, because it is not in your causal capacity to do x, and therefore you are not responsible or accountable for failing to do x. And therefore one is certainly not morally accountable for failing to do x.
I think then that there are good general moral considerations for believing that ought entails can. But, when examining specific ethical systems, it is hard to ground that claim except on utilitarianism or divine command theory. This may be thought of as constituting evidence against ethical systems other than those two. Further, the claim could be furnished in an interesting kantian moral argument for the existence of god. For it could be argued that we ought to bring about the greatest good. But, if god does not exist, then we cannot bring about the greatest good. Conjoined with the claim that ought entails can, this would imply the existence of god.
All food for thought.